ISSA Proceedings 2002 – Strength And Order In Practical Reasoning: Decision-Guiding Argumentation

logo  2002-1Abstract
Beliefs are the only evidence available for an agent making decisions about whether what he wants to do is justified under the circumstances or not. We think the connection between beliefs and goals can be evaluated according to order and strength criteria. Order among supporting reasons constrains the decision-guiding argumentation process to only those decisions that are relevant for the agent while just excluding or postponing the others. Strength determines the expected degree of utility derived from the adoption or non-adoption of a goal. An agent would only be justified in adopting a goal when the reason that supports it remains undefeated.

Introduction
Practical reasoning seems to help the agent in the way of constructing strategies and plans in his pursuit of a better situation for himself. The goals and objectives of an agent can be of diverse nature, from mere intrinsic desires to sub-goals of already intended plans. For instance, to be thirsty is usually a reason for adopting the goal of finding water or some other refreshment to quench one’s thirst. Similarly, the obligation of starting work at nine o’clock every morning can be a sufficient reason for adopting the goal of getting up at half past seven daily. Other goals just respond to exigencies arising from intended plans (e.g. getting a ticket for the Symphony Hall can be just a sub-goal of my intended plan for the weekend). One of the tasks of practical reasoning is to cope with conflict situations of decision-making among an agent’s potential goals. To be sure, sometimes an agent is forced to choose among different relevant options that are jointly incompatible.
Our approach assumes that, though not always, in many cases, the adoption of goals is plan dependent. Generally it happens that a goal cannot be adopted before the agent realizes that he is able to bring a plan about for the occasion. Often an important amount of the value of a goal is directly obtained from the expected utility value of the plan in which it is embedded (Beaudoin 1994). In more detail, the adoption of a goal would be related to three factors: the value of the goal itself, the possibility of constructing a plan pursuing a previously learnt strategy for that goal, and the agent’s commitments to previous plans (Pérez Miranda 1997). Hence to justify the adoption of a goal the rational agent must be able to construct a solid decision-guiding argument. That is, the practical argument constructed for the occasion should remain undefeated after the reasoning process. ‘Practical reasoning is based on an agent’s goals relative to a situation and on his knowledge of what is usually (reasonably expected) to obtain, according to his knowledge of the situation. …Typically, this pragmatic type of reasoning is based on rules or regularities that admit exceptions. Hence the conclusion is based on a kind of plausible reasoning – it represents a type of provisional presumption that could be subject to rejection or revision in the face of the new evidence, or of new developments in the situation’ (Walton 1990: 84).
Once the agent has recognized that a potential goal is obtainable, the next step in determining the adoption of a goal is to detect any incompatibilities between that goal and other possible intended goals derived from previous intended plans or single urgencies that ought to be accomplished without delay. Hence the agent must look for scenarios in which both potential goals and ongoing adopted goals fit together insofar as fulfilling one may be at odds with fulfilling another or with maximum fulfilment of the overall set. We are concerned with explaining how an agent could manage to make these factors fit together appropriately by adopting a behaviour consisting in, so to speak, following some rational patterns.
The evaluative mechanism proposed here is only concerned with those goals that have a motivational or cognitive grounding (see below). According to our model, the rational agent selects only those goals whose supporting reasons are undefeated according to the agent’s doxastic states. The mechanism embodies two levels of decision-making depending on the order and strength of the supporting reasons. An agent only would be justified in adopting a goal when the reason that supports that goal remains undefeated. Read more

image_pdfimage_print
Bookmark and Share

ISSA Proceedings 2002 – A Collaborative Model Of Argumentation In Dyadic Problem-Solving Interactions

logo  2002-11. Introduction
Within a cognitive approach to argumentation, our research deals with the argumentative processes of knowledge co-construction in dialogue (Baker, 1999). From this point of view we have been designing experimental situations favouring argumentation in dyadic problem-solving (Quignard & Baker, 1998; Baker, Quignard, Lund & van Amelsvoort, this volume) over several years, in order to understand the roles of argumentation in the resolution of conceptual problems (Baker, 1998; Baker, Brixhe & Quignard, 2002). Whereas our previous research focussed on socio-cognitive conditions promoting emergence of argumentation between learners (Quignard, 1999 from a previous work of Golder, 1996), in this paper we address the problem of analysing the argumentation processes carried out in problem-solving dialogues and the interactional phenomena by which knowledge is collaboratively elaborated. On one hand, our cognitive approach to argumentation is naturally very closely related to pragmatics studies of dialogue, which aim to describe or analyse the relationships between the use of language and its social or contextual implications in concrete situations. On the other hand, the phenomenon we want to explain – argumentation – has been very well described in normative models of dialectics, which give quite solid bases for defining the limits of argumentation phases, their genuine moves and schemes (attacks and defences) and their rules. The proof of the consistency of such dialectical systems (see fore example Barth & Krabbe, 1982) is another argument in favour of their universal domain of application. These two very different approaches to argumentation are not necessarily to be opposed when the pragmatic foundations of the logic of these systems can be defined with some degree of formality (see for example Quignard & Baker, 1997). Recent developments in pragma-dialectics (van Eemeren & Grootendorst, 1992) have shown the efficiency of this combination, being both a normative and descriptive method for understanding argumentative discourse (van Eemeren et al., 1993) or designing argumentation situations, even for the purposes of learning (see Jackson, 1998).

In fact, – and without playing on words – the previous models of argumentation meet their limits when dialogue is not yet or no longer argumentative. In other terms, when argumentation is too much considered as a verbal activity per se (with its own rules and own moves) there are some difficulties in taking into account cognitive continuum underlying the dialogue, for example rational commitments or problem-solving goals. Krabbe (1988) in an answer to Lorenz (Ibid.) stated that argumentative commitments can obtain in non-argumentative phases (e.g. theses), and thus some argumentative rules could prevail outside argumentative phases. In a later paper with Walton (1995), he tried to provide a logical framework for keeping trace of commitments across different dialogue phases, but that approach cannot be considered as a cognitive model. Another difficulty concerns the definition of a set of argumentative moves for the sake of describing argumentation processes. These moves cannot relate to the general process of dialogue, since they concentrate on purely argumentative objects of discourse: theses and arguments. Therefore, argumentation is disconnected from the pragmatic context of the dialogue from which it emerged, like a dialectical game interrupting a collaborative action. In fact, collaborative action (or the general goal of the dialogue) underlies the argumentation, and may change at any time (for example a conflict dissolution because they need to carry on to another topic). Nevertheless, it is clear that providing two separate sets of speech acts for analysing both parallel processes independently (argumentation and general dialogue) is not a satisfactory solution either since at least for cognitive reasons, these processes are very much linked with each other.

Therefore, a solution would be to derive argumentation moves from general dialogue categories, allowing a unique cognitive action to achieve several functions at a time. The multi-functionality of utterances has been already used in many cases to explain the quantity of things one can do with so few words. Authors like Allwood (1995) or Bunt (1994) have used it to distinguish task-oriented speech acts to dialogue control ones (for interaction management). Our main idea is based on the very pragmatic conception of dialogue from Morris or Clark, who considered dialogue as a verbal problem-solving activity (people use language for collaborating with respect to a given problem). The key point for our concern is to consider argumentation as a specific case of problem-solving, where the problem is the “conflict of avowed opinions” (Barth & Krabbe, op. cit.). Read more

image_pdfimage_print
Bookmark and Share

ISSA Proceedings 2002 – The Limits Of Intuitive Argumentation: Thomas Aquinas On The Communication Between Separated Substances

logo  2002-11. Preliminary remarks
In this paper I make an attempt to analyze Aquinas’ doctrine of the an­gels’ speech (communication between separated substances), both as such and with regard to understanding the limits of intuitive argumentation(i).
It is well known that Thomas was always very clear to distinguish philosophical arguments from theological arguments. However, in the modern reception of Aquinas philosophical arguments, there are prob­lems of interpretation in which we need:
a. to specify their factual or historico-theological background. We would label such problems roughly as historico-factual problems.
b. to reflect logically on what is already factually and contextually known. Many modern commentators of Aquinas have demonstrated that sometimes behind the commonly under­stood passage the deeper conceptual scheme reveals itself only if our in­terpretation is assisted by some kind of ‘mental scalpel’  – scrupulous logical analysis or some other technique of contemporary analytical philosophy. I would label such problems as logico-conceptual ones.

In what follows, I intend to restrict myself to the last sort of prob­lems. This is neither a paper about angelology nor about the history of medieval ideas. My approach will not be apologetic. That is, I will nei­ther try to prove the rightfulness of Aquinas’ arguments nor to refute them. Instead of asking Aquinas’ question: ‘Whether one angel speaks to another?’, I will ask: How would be the conception of angels’ speech, de­scribed by Thomas in the Summa Theologiae la. 107, 1-5 compre­hended in the light of contemporary analytical mind?
The way medieval philosophy approached divine things are, no doubt quite different from what the analytical philosophers are approach­ing today. First, then there is distinction of human knowledge in respect to its possible origins between lumine divinae revelationis and lumine naturalis rationis. It is the epoch-making distinction which covers all the ‘conceptual architectonic’ of the Summa Theologiae, and which, with some qualification can be found in medieval philosophy in general. This is the distinction what states: There are truths that transcend our natural reason but do not contradict it; these truths are the truths of revelation, obtained by saints through the grace of God; evident to angels, and in some way to saints, but not understandable to us. Read more

image_pdfimage_print
Bookmark and Share

ISSA Proceedings 2002 – A Non-Propositional Approach To Emotions In Argument

logo  2002-1In this paper we try to show why it is inadequate to approach emotions within a pragma-dialectic or propositional approach to argument. We confine ourselves to the arguments related to language and discourse. We do not claim that pragma-dialecticians must disappear, what we claim is that the constant movement they try to make in favor of an expansion of their approach is illegitimate. Pragma-dialectics is only a theory of written and highly critical discourse, of computational logical analysis.
Van Eemeren and Houtlosser accept the importance of three levels of rhetorical strategies:
1. the selection of the material,
2. its adaptation to the audience and
3. its presentation.
But the way they analyze them is valid only in their framework. Their claim that we need to start “from the assumption that rhetoric may be considered to operate within a dialectical framework” (van Eemeren and Houtlosser 2000, 2) is not valid beyond the critical, propositional and artificial intelligence approach to argument.
I propose five interrelated lines of thought: the three cited by van Eemeren and Houtlosser and two more:
4. the presence of emotions in speech acts as a nuclear component furnishing motives for action; and
5. the necessity of studying emotions as enculturated phenomena. The difference is that for me the selection operation with which any argumentative discourse begins (the old inventio) is necessarily a relative cultural phenomenon. The relevance of the disposition of the arguments challenges the propositional approach. And the presentation of arguments shows us the inevitability of emotions in language. We cannot consider emotions as a minor component or as a mere accompaniment of the logical-dialectical component. Reason is not divisible; it encompasses the whole of logic, emotion, belief, value and intuition.

1. Emotions and the selection operation
Van Eemeren and Grootendorst (van Eemeren and Grootendorst, 1996) consider the topoï in their logical sense. They perceive that two operations occur in regard to topoï: the selection operation and the warrant operation. They do not care about selection and focus on the warrant role.
Van Eemeren and Houtlosser change the original pragma-dialectical view. They consider the inventio in order to achieve the optimal rhetorical result. The selected moves must be an effective choice made from the available potential moves. The moves must be in such a way adapted to the audience that they comply with auditorial demands.
We cannot discuss this option in the pragma-dialectician terms. What we want to argue is that if there is a warrant function of topoï it is because there was before or at the same time a selection operation. And this selection is rhetorical and is crucial to the argument in a sense that goes beyond the pragma-dialectical interest. If the selection is not well done, then the very possibility of convincing is ruled out, and we will not be able to work on the discourse. This selection still has a logic component but is deeply rooted in intuition and emotion, in what we feel is right and adequate. The conjecture of the neuro-physiologist Antonio Damasio (Damasio, 1994) is that making a decision is an activity guided emotionally by “somatic markers” that filter decisions. And, moreover, decisions are also a cultural and ideological election. And the emotional appeal of a selection can have dramatic consequences even in the most critical discourse, which is scientific discourse. Read more

image_pdfimage_print
Bookmark and Share

ISSA Proceedings 2002 – Rejecting Incommensurability: Traditional Healing And The Biomedical Metanarrative In Africa

logo  2002-1 1. A Differend
The world is a place of dispute, people arguing against one another, and people sometimes remaining silent. We find little solace in these disputes, those of us who are incredulous that is. Incredulity is the new calling of the initiated (Lyotard 2002: XXIV). Beyond modernity is found the place of discomfort, incredulity and the possibility of justice. Justice is never stable nor should it be comfortable for anyone. Discomfort will lead us to justice so long as we leave behind the old justifications fed to us by the demagogues of historical inquiry. There is a place, on the edge of discourse, a place where competing phrase regimens meet, where justice can be discovered or at least attempted for those who do not yet have it. On the precipice of exchange and translation we find discourses that are not commensurable with one another. We find the impossibility of understanding, the need to appropriate if only to find comfort. There are many places where discourses work in spatio-temporal unison. They work side by side but the border is fraught with injustices that cannot always be presented because of the invocation of a particular idiom. The unpresentable must become the presentable through a destabilizing of metanarratives (Lyotard 2002: 82).  Our identity is but one of many; contingency it’s mother. When we hear the call of another phrase regimen, our rules fall off the map of the discursive game played by the Other. When discourses meet and fight for control, appropriation, and litigated meaning, death occurs. However, when discourses meet and do not seek out comfort but discomfort, do not appropriate but bear witness, when the realization that something more is needed than simple cooperation in which silences become enforced across phrase regimens, there is the place where justice can be attempted.
There is a particular clash of phrase regimens happening now in Africa. There, years of colonization have left a history of death, destruction and most of all silence. The current clash and the current point of discomfort for the West at the edge of its language game is the notion of medical knowledge. What counts as medical knowledge is at issue because a solution to the AIDS crisis in Africa has recently become a global concern. The West has a way of litigating between what is medical knowledge and what is not, a set of rules, which cannot be met by traditional methods.
The claims of non-Western medical practitioners often referred to as traditional or spiritual healers are found to be unpresentable or otherwise unprovable within Western idioms. I understand the problematical nature of a homogenizing terms like traditional healer but there are times when essentializing or homogenizing terms can help to show the vastly unpresentable nature of the claims of other discourses within the grand narratives of the West. When Western science and traditional knowledge meet within Western discursive spaces, this is the way in which the delineation has been described:
Because the senses are prone to error, Cartesian philosophy focuses on data, measurement, testing, hypothesizing, objectivity, rationality, replicability, and verifiability. In contrast, indigenous knowledge is subjective because of its basis in historical/cultural experience and uncontrolled observation (Trotti 2001: Section I.B. Indigenous Medicinal Knowledge, para.1). Read more

image_pdfimage_print
Bookmark and Share

ISSA Proceedings 2002 – From Argument Analysis To Cultural Keywords (And Back Again)

logo  2002-11. Introduction
The present investigation aims at bridging recent research on cultural keywords (i.e. words that are particularly revealing of the values of a culture) carried out in various areas of linguistics with the logical and rhetorical analysis of arguments. It will be shown that between these two scientific endeavours there can be a fruitful two-way influence. On the one hand, considerations from argumentation theory can help significantly in the complex task of  hypothesising and testing candidates to the status of keywords in a given culture. On the other hand, our understanding of the functioning in argumentative discourse of endoxa and topoi (as culturally shared values and beliefs and culturally shared rules of inference respectively) can greatly benefit from explicit semantic analyses of cultural keywords. In the article a strategy for this interaction is outlined, motivated and briefly exemplified.

2. Keywords and cultural keywords
What is a keyword? A keyword in the sense the term acquired in the fields of Library Science and Internet search engines, is, as the key metaphor suggests, a means of access to digitally stored information. Apparently, keywords can be used so because they are in some sense representative of a whole body of knowledge to which they are associated. Likewise, the notion of cultural keywords, which introduces a further layer of metaphor, suggests the, admittedly vague, idea of words that are particularly revealing of a culture, that can give access to the inner workings of a culture as a whole, to its fundamental beliefs, values, institutions and customs. In short, of words that explain a culture.
The notion of cultural keyword is often associated to the name of Raymond Williams and to his influential pocket dictionary Keywords: A Vocabulary of Culture and Society (Williams 1976). His study, based for linguistic data on the Oxford English Dictionary, methodologically belongs to a broadly humanist tradition of scholarship, falling somewhere between the history of ideas and what is sometimes called the “external history of language”. In the choice of entries it largely reflects the author’s concerns for social organisation and sometimes his interest for Marxist social theorising: alienation, bourgeois, capitalism, dialectic, hegemony, revolution.
While his contribution to cultural analysis is broadly relevant for the understanding of the cultural and ideological backdrop of a number of contemporary argumentative practices, in what follows we will adopt a much narrower focus, restricting ourselves to the contribution of linguistics proper and, more specifically, to approaches that emphasise the use linguistic semantic methods and theoretical tools, in order to examine how these tools can be brought to bear on the tasks of reconstruction and evaluation of natural language arguments. Read more

image_pdfimage_print
Bookmark and Share
  • About

    Rozenberg Quarterly aims to be a platform for academics, scientists, journalists, authors and artists, in order to offer background information and scholarly reflections that contribute to mutual understanding and dialogue in a seemingly divided world. By offering this platform, the Quarterly wants to be part of the public debate because we believe mutual understanding and the acceptance of diversity are vital conditions for universal progress. Read more...
  • Support

    Rozenberg Quarterly does not receive subsidies or grants of any kind, which is why your financial support in maintaining, expanding and keeping the site running is always welcome. You may donate any amount you wish and all donations go toward maintaining and expanding this website.

    10 euro donation:

    20 euro donation:

    Or donate any amount you like:

    Or:
    ABN AMRO Bank
    Rozenberg Publishers
    IBAN NL65 ABNA 0566 4783 23
    BIC ABNANL2A
    reference: Rozenberg Quarterly

    If you have any questions or would like more information, please see our About page or contact us: info@rozenbergquarterly.com
  • Like us on Facebook

  • Archives